gametheory《经济学理论》 lecture 16: Applications of Sequential and Perfect

Eco514-Game Theory lecture 16: Applications of Sequential and Perfect Bayesian equilibrium Marciano siniscalchi November 16. 1999 Introduction The purpose of this lecture is to help you familiarize with the workings of sequential equi- librium and"sequential equilibrium lite", i.e. perfect Bayesian equilibrium The main focus is the "reputation"result of Kreps and Wilson(1982). You should refer to OR for details and definitions: I am following the textbook quite closely We have already mentioned the Entry Deterrence game. Now consider a K-fold repetition of the game in which an incumbent faces a sequence of K(potential) entrants. It is clear hat, in the subgame in which the last entrant gets a chance to play, the incumbent will Concede. But then, by backward induction, he will also Concede at any previous round This conclusion seems unpalatable. One would expect the chain-store to fight a few times early on so as to deter further entry; yet, this simply cannot occur in equilibrium The Chain-Store Game with Imperfect Information Kreps and Wilson suggest the following way out of the Chain Store Paradox. Assume that with some small probability e >0, the incumbent is"Tough: that is, she really enjoys beating up entrants Consider the behavior of a"Regular"incumbent; clearly, when she faces the last entrant she will Concede if the latter moves In. However, in previous rounds, she may threaten to Fight entry; in this case, if the current entrant moves In and is met with a fight, the following entrant does not learn whether the incumbent is Regular or Tough, because both Fight enty Hence, the posterior probability that the incumbent is Tough remains constant at E, and if this value is such that the following Entrant prefers not to Enter, the incumbent's threat is credible
Eco514—Game Theory Lecture 16: Applications of Sequential and Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Marciano Siniscalchi November 16, 1999 Introduction The purpose of this lecture is to help you familiarize with the workings of sequential equilibrium and “sequential equilibrium lite”, i.e. perfect Bayesian equilibrium. The main focus is the “reputation” result of Kreps and Wilson (1982). You should refer to OR for details and definitions: I am following the textbook quite closely. We have already mentioned the Entry Deterrence game. Now consider a K-fold repetition of the game in which an incumbent faces a sequence of K (potential) entrants. It is clear that, in the subgame in which the last entrant gets a chance to play, the incumbent will Concede. But then, by backward induction, he will also Concede at any previous round. This conclusion seems unpalatable. One would expect the chain-store to fight a few times early on so as to deter further entry; yet, this simply cannot occur in equilibrium. The Chain-Store Game with Imperfect Information Kreps and Wilson suggest the following way out of the Chain Store Paradox. Assume that, with some small probability > 0, the incumbent is “Tough”: that is, she really enjoys beating up entrants. Consider the behavior of a “Regular” incumbent; clearly, when she faces the last entrant, she will Concede if the latter moves In. However, in previous rounds, she may threaten to Fight entry; in this case, if the current entrant moves In and is met with a fight, the following entrant does not learn whether the incumbent is Regular or Tough, because both Fight entry. Hence, the posterior probability that the incumbent is Tough remains constant at , and if this value is such that the following Entrant prefers not to Enter, the incumbent’s threat is credible. 1

hings are not quite so simple in actuality, but Kreps and wilson prove that something very close to this can be supported in a sequential equilibrium; indeed, while there exist other sequential equilibria in which no "reputation"is maintained, there exists a simple restriction on the entrants'beliefs which ensures that the reputation outcome obtains. OR analyze the situation using the notion of PBE, and do not investigate outcome uniqueness. I will follow their treatment, emphasizing certain key steps Model Payoffs in the stage game are as follows 1 In 2 C 0.a b-1, fe Figure 1:0=01=R, T), a>1>b>0, CR=fT=0, fR=CT=-1 To understand the equilibrium strategies, observe first that, if the entrant expect the incumbent to Fight with probability b, her expected payoff from entry equals b(1-b)+(6 )b=0; hence, she is indifferent between staying Out and going In Now, the Tough incumbent will always Fight in the Pbe under consideration. This implies, among other things, that as soon as an entrant observes C in any previous round, he will conclude that the incumbent is Regular, and therefore will enter; so will every subsequent entrant Consider the problem faced by the Regular incumbent who observes entry at some stage k< K. If she Concedes, she gets 0 in the current period, but faces entry thereafter-and hence, by best-responding, she can secure a payoff of no more than 0. Now suppose that she Fights, and that this leads the next entrant to revise her beliefs in such a way that he is indifferent between In and Out; suppose further that, this being the case, the next entrant chooses Out with probability Then, by Fighting the current entrant(and best-responding thereafter), the incumbent also gets a continuation payoff of 0 Thus, following entry, the incumbent is indifferent between F and C. Hence, he entrant will be such that he is indeed indifferent between going In and staying Out o randomize, and the probability of C can be chosen so that the posterior beliefs of th Notice that this argument relies heavily on the equilibrium assumption!
Things are not quite so simple in actuality, but Kreps and Wilson prove that something very close to this can be supported in a sequential equilibrium; indeed, while there exist other sequential equilibria in which no “reputation” is maintained, there exists a simple restriction on the entrants’ beliefs which ensures that the reputation outcome obtains. OR analyze the situation using the notion of PBE, and do not investigate outcome uniqueness. I will follow their treatment, emphasizing certain key steps. Model Payoffs in the stage game are as follows: b, cθ q 1 0,a Out In q 2 F C b − 1, fθ Figure 1: Θ = Θ1 = {R, T}, a > 1 > b > 0, cR = fT = 0, fR = cT = −1. To understand the equilibrium strategies, observe first that, if the entrant expect the incumbent to Fight with probability b, her expected payoff from entry equals b(1 − b) + (b − 1)b = 0; hence, she is indifferent between staying Out and going In. Now, the Tough incumbent will always Fight in the PBE under consideration. This implies, among other things, that as soon as an entrant observes C in any previous round, he will conclude that the incumbent is Regular, and therefore will enter; so will every subsequent entrant. Consider the problem faced by the Regular incumbent who observes entry at some stage k < K. If she Concedes, she gets 0 in the current period, but faces entry thereafter—and hence, by best-responding, she can secure a payoff of no more than 0. Now suppose that she Fights, and that this leads the next entrant to revise her beliefs in such a way that he is indifferent between In and Out; suppose further that, this being the case, the next entrant chooses Out with probability 1 a . Then, by Fighting the current entrant (and best-responding thereafter), the incumbent also gets a continuation payoff of 0. Thus, following entry, the incumbent is indifferent between F and C. Hence, he can randomize, and the probability of C can be chosen so that the posterior beliefs of the next entrant will be such that he is indeed indifferent between going In and staying Out. [Notice that this argument relies heavily on the equilibrium assumption!] 2

Equilibrium Refer to OR for definitions The basic idea is as follows The first k*-1 entrants will stay Out, where k*= mink: b-k+1>6. Hence, nothing will be learned about the incumbents type in equilibrium during the first k*-1 rounds: t(h)< h* implies u(h(T) If, however, one of the first k*-1 entrants does enter, the Regular incumbent Fights Note that this implies that, even in this case, nothing will be learned about the in- cumbent's type; hence, the continuation play following such a deviation resembles equilibrium play Entrant k" goes In if E=u(h)(r)<b-k+, and randomizes between In and Out in case of equality. In either case, if there is entry, the Incumbent reacts by randomizing between C and F. If there is no entry, beliefs are unchanged, so the next entrant tainly enters Beliefs are thus updated via Bayes'rule. Thus, as soon as the Incumbent plays C, the following Entrants all choose In. Also, whenever an entrant goes In and the incumbent Fights. the next entrant is indifferent between In and Out. and hence randomizes e In the last round. the Incumbent Concedes You should convince yourself that the equilibrium described in OR achieves precisely this. In particular, you should see that, whenever u(h)(T)=b-k+, the probability of a Fight in the following round is exactly b (so the next entrant is indeed willing to randomize Also, the posterior probability of T given F is bk-k, as per the equilibrium beliefs. Finally as claimed in the previous section, it is easy to see that, following entry at or after Stage k*, the continuation payoff to the incumbent if he plays F is indeed 0, as it must be to justify randomization Plausible beliefs The preceding arguments go a long way(but not all the way) towards proving that reputation can be maintained in a PBE. However, the original result due to Kreps and wilson is stronger first, they use the notion of Sequential Equilibrium; second, they show that any SE which satisfies a certain restriction on beliefs induces the reputation outcome. The restriction on beliefs has the following form: consider two histories h and h' such that h' differs from h only in that, at some subhistories following entry, the incumbent
Equilibrium [Refer to OR for definitions] The basic idea is as follows. • The first k ∗ − 1 entrants will stay Out, where k ∗ = min{k : b K − k + 1 ≥ }. Hence, nothing will be learned about the incumbent’s type in equilibrium during the first k ∗ − 1 rounds: t(h) < k∗ implies µ(h)(T) = . • If, however, one of the first k ∗ − 1 entrants does enter, the Regular incumbent Fights. Note that this implies that, even in this case, nothing will be learned about the incumbent’s type; hence, the continuation play following such a deviation resembles equilibrium play. • Entrant k ∗ goes In if = µ(h)(T) < bK−k ∗+1, and randomizes between In and Out in case of equality. In either case, if there is entry, the Incumbent reacts by randomizing between C and F. If there is no entry, beliefs are unchanged, so the next entrant certainly enters. • Beliefs are thus updated via Bayes’ rule. Thus, as soon as the Incumbent plays C, the following Entrants all choose In. Also, whenever an entrant goes In and the incumbent Fights, the next entrant is indifferent between In and Out, and hence randomizes. • In the last round, the Incumbent Concedes. You should convince yourself that the equilibrium described in OR achieves precisely this. In particular, you should see that, whenever µ(h)(T) = b K−k+1, the probability of a Fight in the following round is exactly b (so the next entrant is indeed willing to randomize). Also, the posterior probability of T given F is b K−k , as per the equilibrium beliefs. Finally, as claimed in the previous section, it is easy to see that, following entry at or after Stage k ∗ , the continuation payoff to the incumbent if he plays F is indeed 0, as it must be to justify randomization. Plausible Beliefs The preceding arguments go a long way (but not all the way) towards proving that reputation can be maintained in a PBE. However, the original result due to Kreps and Wilson is stronger: first, they use the notion of Sequential Equilibrium; second, they show that any SE which satisfies a certain restriction on beliefs induces the reputation outcome. The restriction on beliefs has the following form: consider two histories h and h 0 such that h 0 differs from h only in that, at some subhistories following entry, the incumbent 3

Concedes instead of Fighting. Then it must be the case that u(h)(r)>(h(R). This makes sense-and Kreps and Wilson deem beliefs which satisfy this condition plausible. The key point is that one could construct "strange"equilibria in which reacting to off- equilibrium entry with F induces subsequent entrants to believe that the incumbent is Reg- ular: this could engender further entry out of equilibrium. If this is the case, the incumbent might Concede early in the game, in order to avoid ( being identified as a regular type !) You can convince yourself that the beliefs used in the construction of our "reputational luilibrium"are indeed plausible Building vs. Maintaining a Reputation Note that, in the equilibrium we have constructed, essentially nothing happens in the first ke*-1 stages. Thus, there is no sense in which the incumbent "builds a reputation"for being tough. This can only be said of the last few stages-but note that the length of the randomization phase only depends on 6, and not on the overall length of the game. Thus, one may have a very protracted play phase in which no reputation is built, and a comparatively tiny one in which actual reputation building occurs Rather, this story has to do with maintaining a reputation for toughness. Also, it should be apparent that the result depends crucially on the equilibrium assumption: consider the delicate interlocking of randomizations
Concedes instead of Fighting. Then it must be the case that µ(h)(R) ≥ µ(h 0 )(R). This makes sense—and Kreps and Wilson deem beliefs which satisfy this condition plausible. The key point is that one could construct “strange” equilibria in which reacting to off- equilibrium entry with F induces subsequent entrants to believe that the incumbent is Regular: this could engender further entry out of equilibrium. If this is the case, the incumbent might Concede early in the game, in order to avoid (!) being identified as a regular type (!!!). You can convince yourself that the beliefs used in the construction of our “reputational equilibrium” are indeed plausible. Building vs. Maintaining a Reputation Note that, in the equilibrium we have constructed, essentially nothing happens in the first k ∗ − 1 stages. Thus, there is no sense in which the incumbent “builds a reputation” for being tough. This can only be said of the last few stages—but note that the length of the randomization phase only depends on , and not on the overall length of the game. Thus, one may have a very protracted play phase in which no reputation is built, and a comparatively tiny one in which actual reputation building occurs. Rather, this story has to do with maintaining a reputation for toughness. Also, it should be apparent that the result depends crucially on the equilibrium assumption: consider the delicate interlocking of randomizations. 4
按次数下载不扣除下载券;
注册用户24小时内重复下载只扣除一次;
顺序:VIP每日次数-->可用次数-->下载券;
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Problem Set 1: Due Friday.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Problem Set 2: Due Thursday.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Marciano siniscalchi.doc
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Problem Set 4: Due Tuesday, November.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Problem Set 3: Due Thursday, October 28.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Problem set 5: Due Tuesday, November 23.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 12: Repeated Games.pdf
- 经济学—微观经济学——微观经济学 (总复习讲解).ppt
- 经济学—微观经济学——总体均衡与福利经济学概论.ppt
- 经济学—微观经济学——关于分配理论的讲解.ppt
- 经济学—微观经济学——产业组织理论讲解.ppt
- 经济学—微观经济学——生产者理论概论.ppt
- 经济学《微观经济学》:消费者理论讲解(The Theory of Consumer).ppt
- 经济学—微观经济学——弹性理论(The Theory of Elasticity).ppt
- 经济学—微观经济学——微观经济学的形成讲解.ppt
- 经济学—微观经济学——《经济学原理》课程的重要性.ppt
- 东北农业大学《农业经济学》课程教学资源(PPT课件)农业产业化经营.ppt
- 东北农业大学《农业经济学》课程教学资源(PPT课件)农业经济的微观组织.ppt
- 东北农业大学《农业经济学》课程教学资源(PPT课件)农业资金.ppt
- 东北农业大学《农业经济学》课程教学资源(PPT课件)农业技术进步.ppt
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 8.5: More on Auctions.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 lecture 11: Subgame perfection.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 14: General Extensive Games.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 1 Game Theory Multiperson Decision Theory.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 ecture 6: Interactive Epistemology(1).pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 10: Extensive Games with(Almost) Perfect.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 ecture 7: Interactive Epistemology(2).pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 15: Sequential equilibrium.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 13: Repeated Games(2).pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 2:(Iterated) Best Response Operators.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 4: Games with Payoff Uncertainty(1).pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 gnawing game Marciano siniscalchi January 10, 2000.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 The Trembling Hand: Normal-Form Analysis and Extensive-Form Implications.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Forward Induction Marciano siniscalchi January 10, 2000.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 3: Nash equilibrium.pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 5: Games with Payoff Uncertainty(2).pdf
- gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 5: Games with Payoff Uncertainty(2.pdf
- 广东外语外贸大学:《国际贸易理论与政策》 贸易理论篇分析与研究.doc
- 中国人民大学:《经贸知识英语》 概论.ppt
- 《宏观经济学》课程PPT教学课件:第四章 货币市场的均衡.ppt